Between Marx, Marxism, and Marxisms – Ways of Reading Marx’s Theory

by Ingo Elbe on October 23, 2013

(This article was originally published by Viewpoint Magazine and is reposted with their permission.)

The objec­tive of the fol­low­ing obser­va­tions is to offer a rough overview of cen­tral ways of read­ing Marx’s the­ory. These are to be pre­sented – by means of a few selected top­ics – as Marxisms that can be rel­a­tively clearly delim­ited from one another, and the his­tory of their recep­tion and influ­ence will be eval­u­ated with regard to the common-sense under­stand­ing of “Marx­ist theory.”

A dis­tinc­tion will be made between the hith­erto pre­dom­i­nant inter­pre­ta­tion of Marx, pri­mar­ily asso­ci­ated with polit­i­cal par­ties (tra­di­tional Marx­ism, Marx­ism in the sin­gu­lar, if you will), and the dis­si­dent, crit­i­cal forms of recep­tion of Marx (Marxisms in the plural), with their respec­tive claims of a “return to Marx.” The first inter­pre­ta­tion is under­stood as a prod­uct and process of a restricted read­ing of Marx, in part emerg­ing from the “exo­teric” layer of Marx’s work, which updates tra­di­tional par­a­digms in polit­i­cal econ­omy, the the­ory of his­tory, and phi­los­o­phy. Sys­tem­atized and ele­vated to a doc­trine by Engels, Kaut­sky, et al, it suc­cumbs to the mys­ti­fi­ca­tions of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion and cul­mi­nates in the apolo­getic sci­ence of Marxism-Leninism. The other two inter­pre­ta­tions, specif­i­cally West­ern Marx­ism as well as the Ger­man neue Marx-Lektüre (“new read­ing of Marx”), usu­ally explore the “eso­teric” con­tent of Marx’s cri­tique and analy­sis of soci­ety, often con­sum­mated out­side of insti­tu­tion­al­ized, cumu­la­tive research pro­grams, by iso­lated actors in the style of an “under­ground Marxism.”

In order to char­ac­ter­ize both ways of read­ing, some strongly trun­cated the­ses, lim­ited to a few aspects, must suf­fice. In par­tic­u­lar the ambi­tious propo­si­tion, first for­mu­lated by Karl Korsch, of an “appli­ca­tion of the mate­ri­al­ist con­cep­tion of his­tory to the mate­ri­al­ist con­cep­tion of his­tory itself” – one that goes beyond the mere pre­sen­ta­tion of intel­lec­tual his­tory, towards an imma­nent the­o­ret­i­cal cri­tique that crit­i­cally con­sid­ers the con­nec­tion between his­tor­i­cal forms of praxis and the­o­ret­i­cal for­ma­tions of Marx­ism – can­not be car­ried out here. In addi­tion, a con­sid­er­a­tion of those read­ings which are crit­i­cal of Marx or Marx­ism can also be dis­re­garded here, inso­far as their pic­ture of Marx usu­ally cor­re­sponds to that of tra­di­tional Marxism.

I there­fore begin with the hege­monic inter­pre­ta­tive model of tra­di­tional Marx­ism, and only at the end of my pre­sen­ta­tion will I con­clude with a few pos­i­tive deter­mi­na­tions of what I regard as the fun­da­men­tal sys­tem­atic inten­tion of Marx’s work. I do this pri­mar­ily because a dif­fer­en­ti­ated read­ing of Marx’s work can only be gained in the course of the learn­ing processes of West­ern Marx­ism and the neue Marx-Lektüre.

I. Marx­ism

The term “Marx­ism” was prob­a­bly first used in the year 1879 by the Ger­man Social Demo­c­rat Franz Mehring to char­ac­ter­ize Marx’s the­ory, and estab­lished itself at the end of the 1880s as a dis­cur­sive weapon used by both crit­ics and defend­ers of “Marx’s teach­ings.” The birth of a “Marx­ist school,” how­ever, is unan­i­mously dated back to the pub­li­ca­tion of Anti-Dühring by Friedrich Engels in the year 1878, and the sub­se­quent recep­tion of this work by Karl Kaut­sky, Eduard Berstein, et al. Engels’ writ­ings – even if the terms “Marx­ism” or “dialec­ti­cal mate­ri­al­ism,” the self-applied labels of tra­di­tional read­ings, do not yet appear in them – sup­plied entire gen­er­a­tions of read­ers, Marx­ists as well as anti-Marxists, with the inter­pre­ta­tive model through which Marx’s work was per­ceived. In par­tic­u­lar, the review of Marx’s Con­tri­bu­tion to the Cri­tique of Polit­i­cal Econ­omy (1859), the late work Lud­wig Feuer­bach and the End of Clas­si­cal Ger­man Phi­los­o­phy (1886), and the sup­ple­ment to Vol­ume III of Cap­i­tal(1894/95), achieved an influ­ence that can hardly be under­es­ti­mated. Above all, how­ever, it was Anti-Dühring that was to be styl­ized as the text­book of Marx­ist the­ory as well as a pos­i­tive depic­tion of a “Marx­ist world­view”: for Kaut­sky, “there is no other book that has con­tributed so much to the under­stand­ing of Marx­ism. Marx’s Cap­i­tal is greater. But it was first through Anti-Dühring that we learned to cor­rectly read and under­stand Cap­i­tal.” And for Lenin, it is one of the “hand­books of every class-conscious worker.”1

At the same time, a gen­eral char­ac­ter­is­tic of the his­tory of “Marx­ism” is con­sum­mated: the ini­tia­tors of the the­o­ret­i­cal cor­pus regard it as “unnec­es­sary […] to them­selves make an appear­ance as eponyms […] the eponyms are not the real speak­ers.” In many respects, Marx­ism is Engels’ work and for that rea­son actu­ally an Engel­sism. In what fol­lows I will name only two points which an ide­ol­o­gized and restricted recep­tion of Marx could draw upon.

I.1 The Ontological-Determinist Tendency

Sci­en­tific social­ism was con­ceived of as an onto­log­i­cal sys­tem, a “sci­ence of the big pic­ture.” The mate­ri­al­ist dialec­tic func­tions here as a “gen­eral law of devel­op­ment of nature, soci­ety, and thought,”2 while nature serves for Engels as a “proof of dialec­tics.”3 Engels already under­takes a false anal­ogy between historical-social processes and nat­ural phe­nom­ena by the mere fact that in his elu­ci­da­tion of the main fea­tures of the dialec­tic, ref­er­ence to sub­ject and object is miss­ing. “Nega­tion of the nega­tion” or the “trans­for­ma­tion of quan­tity into qual­ity” are iden­ti­fied in the changes in the phys­i­cal state of water or in the devel­op­ment of a grain of bar­ley. Against a sta­tic point of view, dialec­tic is sup­posed to demon­strate the “becom­ing,” the “tran­si­tory char­ac­ter” of all exis­tence,4 and is bound to tra­di­tional dichotomies of the phi­los­o­phy of con­scious­ness, such as the so-called “great basic ques­tion of all phi­los­o­phy “as to which com­po­nent of the rela­tion­ship between “think­ing and being” has pri­macy.5 The dialec­tic is split into “two sets of laws,” into the dialec­tic of “the exter­nal world” and the dialec­tic of “human thought,” whereby the lat­ter is under­stood to be merely a pas­sive men­tal image of the for­mer.6 Engels con­stricts – even dis­torts – the three ele­men­tary praxis-philosophical motifs of Marx, which he had par­tially still advo­cated in his ear­lier writings:

  1. The recog­ni­tion that not only the object, but also the obser­va­tion of the object is his­tor­i­cally and prac­ti­cally medi­ated,7 not exter­nal to the his­tory of the mode of pro­duc­tion. Against this, Engels empha­sizes that “the mate­ri­al­ist out­look on nature means noth­ing more than the sim­ple con­cep­tion of nature just as it is, with­out alien addi­tion.”8 The naive real­ism of the the­ory of reflec­tion sys­tem­atized by Lenin9 and oth­ers – which falls prey to the rei­fied appear­ance of imme­di­acy of that which is socially medi­ated, the fetishism of an in-itself of that which exists only via a his­tor­i­cally deter­mined frame­work of human activ­ity – already obtains its foun­da­tion in Engels’ writ­ings.10 As “things refer to con­scious­ness and con­scious­ness refers to things,”11 the con­cepts of praxis and the sub­jec­tive medi­a­tion of the object, as well as ideology-critical con­sid­er­a­tions, have hardly any place in this paradigm.
  2. The con­cept of Natur­wüch­sigkeit (“the state of being nat­u­rally derived”), which Engels had used in The Ger­man Ide­ol­ogy in a neg­a­tive sense, is now turned into a pos­i­tive con­cept. The sub­la­tion of spe­cific social laws rest­ing upon the uncon­scious­ness of social actors is no longer pos­tu­lated; rather, Engels pos­tu­lates the con­scious appli­ca­tion of “the gen­eral laws of motion […] of the exter­nal world.”12
  3. If Marx writes in the The­ses on Feuer­bach that “all mys­ter­ies which lead the­ory to mys­ti­cism find their ratio­nal solu­tion in human prac­tice and in the com­pre­hen­sion of this prac­tice,”13 Engels reduces praxis to the exper­i­men­tal activ­ity of the nat­ural sci­ences.14 Admit­tedly, ambiva­lences and praxis-philosophical motifs can also be found in the writ­ings of the late Engels, which were largely blot­ted out by the epigones. Nonethe­less, Engels, bundling together the sci­en­tism of his epoch, paves the way for a mech­a­nis­tic and fatal­is­tic con­cep­tion of his­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism by shift­ing the accent from a the­ory of social praxis to one of a con­tem­pla­tive, reflection-theory doc­trine of development.

The vul­gar evo­lu­tion­ism of nineteenth-century Euro­pean Social Democ­racy is a nearly ubiq­ui­tous phe­nom­e­non.15 For that rea­son, it is not just for Kaut­sky, Bern­stein, and Bebel that the deter­min­is­tic con­cept of devel­op­ment and the rev­o­lu­tion­ary meta­physic of a prov­i­den­tial mis­sion of the pro­le­tariat16 occupy a cen­tral place in Marx­ist doc­trine. Accord­ingly, human­ity is sub­or­di­nated to a “sci­en­tif­i­cally ver­i­fi­able” automa­tism of lib­er­a­tion. That which presents itself in the mod­ern sci­en­tific garb of a fetishism of laws is ulti­mately noth­ing other than a his­tor­i­cal meta­physic with a social­ist sig­na­ture17: pre­cisely the inver­sion of sub­ject and object that Marx had crit­i­cized. A process con­sum­mated behind the back of social actors is attrib­uted a morally qual­i­fied aim.18 Ulti­mately, in the Erfurt Pro­gram of the Ger­man Social Demo­c­ra­tic Party, this rev­o­lu­tion­ary pas­siv­ity19 is cod­i­fied at an offi­cial level as con­sis­tent Marx­ism: the task of the party is to remain braced for an event that will “nec­es­sar­ily” hap­pen even with­out inter­ven­tion, “not to make the rev­o­lu­tion, but rather to take advan­tage of it.”20 The onto­log­i­cal ori­en­ta­tion and the ency­clopaedic char­ac­ter of Engels’ delib­er­a­tions also feed the ten­dency to inter­pret sci­en­tific social­ism as a com­pre­hen­sive pro­le­tar­ian world­view. Ulti­mately, Lenin will present the “Marx­ist doc­trine” as “omnipo­tent,” a “com­pre­hen­sive and har­mo­nious” doc­trine that “pro­vides men with an inte­gral world out­look.”21 Cor­re­spond­ingly, the neg­a­tive con­cept of ide­ol­ogy is neu­tral­ized into a cat­e­gory for the deter­mi­nate being of con­scious­ness in general.

All of these devel­op­ments, which undoubt­edly con­sti­tute a the­o­ret­i­cal regres­sion, ulti­mately cul­mi­nate in the the­ory of “Marxism-Leninism” con­ceived of by Abram Deborin and Josef Stalin. If for Lenin, Marx­ism con­sti­tutes – despite all empha­sis upon the polit­i­cal – a “pro­found doc­trine of devel­op­ment”22 that calls atten­tion to breaks and leaps in nature and soci­ety, in the case of Marxism-Leninism the naturalist-objectivist cur­rent is ele­vated to a state doc­trine. The cen­tral argu­men­ta­tive fig­ure will be: what is valid for nature must also be valid for his­tory. Or: nature makes leaps, there­fore so does his­tory. Polit­i­cal praxis is thus under­stood as the con­sum­ma­tion of his­tor­i­cal laws. This impres­sive logic is per­fected in Stalin’s work “Dialec­ti­cal and His­tor­i­cal Mate­ri­al­ism” – for decades an author­i­ta­tive work in the Marx­ist the­ory of the East­ern Bloc. His­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism stands for the “appli­ca­tion” and “exten­sion” of onto­log­i­cal prin­ci­ples to soci­ety, which implies an epis­te­mo­log­i­cal essen­tial­ism (a the­ory of reflec­tion, which in the form of Dialec­ti­cal Mate­ri­al­ism con­ceives of “being” and “think­ing” inde­pen­dent of the con­cept of praxis) and a soci­o­log­i­cal nat­u­ral­ism (a devel­op­men­tal logic – to be “con­sciously applied” or “accel­er­ated” by the party as the high­est tech­no­cratic instance23 – exist­ing inde­pen­dent of human agency).24

I.2 The His­tori­cist Inter­pre­ta­tion of the Form-Genetic Method

If Lenin’s state­ment that “none of the Marx­ists for the past half cen­tury have under­stood Marx” – a dic­tum that in this case how­ever also applies to Lenin him­self – has any valid­ity, then it is cer­tainly with regard to the inter­pre­ta­tion of the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy. Even 100 years after the pub­li­ca­tion of the first vol­ume of Cap­i­tal, Engels’ com­men­tary was widely regarded as the sole legit­i­mate and ade­quate assess­ment of Marx’s cri­tique of econ­omy. No read­ing in the Marx­ist tra­di­tion was as uncon­tro­ver­sial as the one casu­ally devel­oped by Engels in texts such as the review of Marx’s Con­tri­bu­tion to the Cri­tique of Polit­i­cal Econ­omy (1859) or the sup­ple­ment to Vol­ume III of Cap­i­tal (1894). Here, con­sid­er­ably more explic­itly than in the objec­tivist con­cep­tion of his­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism, Marx­ism is Engelsism.

Against the back­ground of his con­cep­tion of reflec­tion, Engels inter­prets the first chap­ter of Cap­i­tal as a simul­ta­ne­ously log­i­cal and his­tor­i­cal pre­sen­ta­tion of “sim­ple com­mod­ity pro­duc­tion” devel­op­ing toward the rela­tions of cap­i­tal­ist wage labor, “only stripped of the his­tor­i­cal form and divert­ing chance occur­rences.”25 The term “log­i­cal” in this con­text basi­cally means noth­ing more than “sim­pli­fied.” The method of pre­sen­ta­tion, the sequence of cat­e­gories (com­mod­ity, the ele­men­tary, expanded, and gen­eral forms of value, money, cap­i­tal) in the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy is accord­ingly “sim­ply the reflec­tion, in abstract and the­o­ret­i­cally con­sis­tent form, of the his­tor­i­cal course.”26 The exam­i­na­tion of the gen­e­sis of the money form is under­stood as the descrip­tion of “an actual event which really took place at some time or other” and not as “an abstract men­tal process that takes place solely in our mind.”27 In no other pas­sage of his work does Engels so dras­ti­cally reduce his­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism to a vul­gar empiri­cism and his­tori­cism, as is made evi­dent by his asso­cia­tive chain “mate­ri­al­ism – empir­i­cally ver­i­fi­able facts – real process” vs. “ide­al­ism – abstract thought process – purely abstract territory.”

With the “logical-historical” method, Engels pro­vides a catch­phrase that will be recited and stressed ad nau­seam in the Marx­ist ortho­doxy. Karl Kaut­sky, in his enor­mously influ­en­tial pre­sen­ta­tions, under­stood Cap­i­tal to be an “essen­tially his­tor­i­cal work”28: “Marx was charged with rec­og­niz­ing cap­i­tal to be a his­tor­i­cal cat­e­gory and to prove its emer­gence in his­tory, rather than men­tally con­struct­ing it.”29 Rudolf Hil­fer­d­ing also claims that “in accor­dance with the dialec­tic method, con­cep­tual evo­lu­tion runs par­al­lel through­out with his­tor­i­cal evo­lu­tion.”30 Both Marxism-Leninism31 and West­ern Marx­ism32 fol­low Hil­fer­d­ing in this assess­ment. But if the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy is inter­preted as his­to­ri­og­ra­phy, then con­se­quen­tially the cat­e­gories at the begin­ning must cor­re­spond directly to empir­i­cal objects, for exam­ple a dubi­ous pre-capitalist com­mod­ity not deter­mined by price,33 and the analy­sis of the form of value must begin with the depic­tion of a coin­ci­den­tal, money­less inter­ac­tion of two com­mod­ity own­ers – with Engels’ so-called “sim­ple pro­duc­tion of com­modi­ties,”34 an eco­nomic epoch he dates from 6000 BC to the 15th cen­tury AD. Accord­ing to this con­cep­tion, Marx’s law of value35 oper­ates at times in this epoch in a pure form “unadul­ter­ated” by the cat­e­gory of price, which Engels illus­trates with the feigned exam­ple of a money­less “exchange” between medieval peas­ants and artisans.

Here we are deal­ing with a trans­par­ent social inter­re­la­tion­ship between imme­di­ate pro­duc­ers who are at the same time the own­ers of their means of pro­duc­tion, in which one pro­ducer labors under the watch­ful eye of the other, and there­fore “the peas­ant of the Mid­dle Ages knew fairly accu­rately the labor-time required for the man­u­fac­ture of the arti­cles obtained by him in barter.”36 Under the con­di­tions of this “nat­ural exchange”, it is not some nor­ma­tive cri­te­rion that is for him “the only suit­able mea­sure for the quan­ti­ta­tive deter­mi­na­tion of the val­ues to be exchanged,”37 but rather the abstrac­tion of a labor-time con­sciously and directly mea­sured by the actors. Nei­ther the peas­ant nor the arti­san is so stu­pid as to exchange unequal quan­ti­ties of labor38: “No other exchange is pos­si­ble in the whole period of peas­ant nat­ural econ­omy than that in which the exchanged quan­ti­ties of com­modi­ties tend to be mea­sured more and more accord­ing to the amounts of labor embod­ied in them.”39 Accord­ing to Engels, the value of a com­mod­ity is deter­mined con­sciously by the labor, mea­sured in time, of indi­vid­ual pro­duc­ers. In this the­ory of value, money does not play a con­sti­tu­tive role. On the one hand, it is an expe­di­ent and lubri­cant to trade that is exter­nal to value, but on the other it serves to obscure the sub­stance of value: sud­denly, instead of exchang­ing accord­ing to hours of labor, at some point exchange is con­ducted by means of cows and then pieces of gold. The ques­tion of how this notion of every com­mod­ity being its own labor-money40 can be rec­on­ciled with the con­di­tions of pri­vate pro­duc­tion based upon the divi­sion of labor is not posed by Engels. Engels – as will be elab­o­rated by the neue Marx-Lektüre – prac­tices exactly what Marx crit­i­cizes in the case of the clas­si­cal econ­o­mists, above all Adam Smith: a pro­jec­tion onto the past of the illu­sory notion of appro­pri­a­tion through one’s own labor, which in fact only exists in cap­i­tal­ism; neglect of the nec­es­sary con­nec­tion between value and form of value41; a trans­for­ma­tion of the “objec­tive equal­iza­tion” of unequal acts of labor con­sum­mated by the objec­tive social rela­tion­ship itself into a merely sub­jec­tive con­sid­er­a­tion of social actors.42

Up until the 1960s, Engels’ the­o­rems con­tin­ued to be passed on undis­puted. Along with his for­mula (once again taken from Hegel) of free­dom being the insight into neces­sity, and the draw­ing of par­al­lels between nat­ural laws and social processes, they gave sus­te­nance to a social-technological “con­cept of eman­ci­pa­tion,” accord­ing to the fol­low­ing premise: social neces­sity (above all the law of value), which oper­ates anar­chi­cally and uncon­trolled in cap­i­tal­ism, will be, by means of Marx­ism as a sci­ence of the objec­tive laws of nature and soci­ety, man­aged and applied accord­ing to a plan. Not the dis­ap­pear­ance of cap­i­tal­ist form-determinations, but rather their alter­na­tive use char­ac­ter­izes this “social­ism of adjec­tives” (this term comes from Robert Kurz) and “social­ist polit­i­cal econ­omy.”43 There is a sig­nif­i­cant dis­pro­por­tion between, on the one hand, the empha­sis upon the “his­tor­i­cal,” and on the other, the absence of a his­tor­i­cally spe­cific and socio-theoretically reflected con­cept of eco­nomic objec­tiv­ity. This is made evi­dent by the irrel­e­vance of the con­cept of social form in the dis­cus­sions of tra­di­tional Marx­ism, in which it is at most is con­sid­ered to be s a cat­e­gory for ideal or mar­ginal cir­cum­stances, but not a con­sti­tu­tive char­ac­ter­is­tic of Marx’s sci­en­tific rev­o­lu­tion.44

I.3 The Cri­tique of the Con­tent of the State

Engels’ the­o­ret­i­cal state­ments con­cern­ing the state in The Ori­gin of the Fam­ilyLud­wig Feuer­bachAnti-Dühring, and his cri­tique of the Erfurt draft pro­gram of the SPD from 1891, con­sti­tute the source of the tra­di­tional Marx­ist con­cep­tion of the state. InLud­wig Feuer­bach, Engels states that the fact that all needs in class soci­eties are artic­u­lated through the will of the state is “the for­mal aspect of the mat­ter – the one which is self-evident.”45 The main ques­tion of a mate­ri­al­ist the­ory of the state, how­ever, is “what is the con­tent of this merely for­mal will – of the indi­vid­ual as well as of the state – and whence is this con­tent derived? Why is just this willed and not some­thing else?”46 The result of this purely content-based ques­tion con­cern­ing the will of the state is for Engels the recog­ni­tion “that in mod­ern his­tory the will of the state is, on the whole, deter­mined by the chang­ing needs of civil soci­ety, by the supremacy of this or that class, in the last resort, by the devel­op­ment of the pro­duc­tive forces and rela­tions of exchange.”47 Fur­ther­more, in his delib­er­a­tions in The Ori­gin of the Fam­ilyEngels works with universal-historical cat­e­gories onto which mod­ern des­ig­na­tions like “pub­lic author­ity” are pro­jected, and con­stantly assumes “direct rela­tions of dom­i­na­tion, imme­di­ate forms of class rule”48 in order to explain “the” state, which is con­se­quen­tially under­stood as a mere instru­ment of the rul­ing class. From this content-fixated and universal-historical way of con­sid­er­ing the state, it can be deduced that Engels loses sight of the actu­ally inter­est­ing ques­tion, namely as to why the class con­tent in cap­i­tal­ism takes on the spe­cific form of pub­lic author­ity.49 The per­sonal def­i­n­i­tion of class rule extracted from pre-capitalist social for­ma­tions ulti­mately leads to reduc­ing the anony­mous form of class rule insti­tu­tion­al­ized in the state to a mere ide­o­log­i­cal illu­sion, which, in the man­ner of the the­ory of priestly decep­tion, is inter­preted as a prod­uct of state tac­tics of decep­tion. Engels in any case attempts to make the class char­ac­ter of the state plau­si­ble by refer­ring to “plain cor­rup­tion of offi­cials” and “an alliance between the gov­ern­ment and the stock exchange.”50 Nonethe­less, in Engels’ work there still exists, despite the pre­dom­i­nance of the instrumentalist/content-fixated per­spec­tive, an unmedi­ated coex­is­tence between the deter­mi­na­tion of the state as the “state of the cap­i­tal­ists” and of the state as “ideal total cap­i­tal­ist.”51 The last def­i­n­i­tion con­ceives of the state “not as a tool of the bour­geoisie […] but rather as an entity of bour­geois soci­ety,”52 and an “organ­i­sa­tion that bour­geois soci­ety takes on in order to sup­port the gen­eral exter­nal con­di­tions of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion against the encroach­ments as well of the work­ers as of indi­vid­ual cap­i­tal­ists.”53 But the spe­cific for­mal aspect of mod­ern state­hood is not yet explained by this ref­er­ence to func­tional mech­a­nisms. Engels also paved the way for the the­ory of state-monopoly cap­i­tal­ism.54 In the Cri­tique of the Draft Social-Democratic Pro­gram of 1891 he writes: “I am famil­iar with cap­i­tal­ist pro­duc­tion as a social form, or an eco­nomic phase; cap­i­tal­ist pri­vate pro­duc­tion being a phe­nom­e­nonwhich in one form or another is encoun­tered in that phase. What is cap­i­tal­ist pri­vatepro­duc­tion? Pro­duc­tion by sep­a­rate entre­pre­neurs, which is increas­ingly becom­ing an excep­tion. Cap­i­tal­ist pro­duc­tion by joint-stock com­pa­nies is no longer pri­vate pro­duc­tion but pro­duc­tion on behalf of many asso­ci­ated peo­ple. And when we pass on from joint-stock com­pa­nies to trusts, which dom­i­nate and monop­o­lise whole branches of indus­try, this puts an end not only to pri­vate pro­duc­tion but also to plan­less­ness.”55Finally, in Anti-Dühring Engels writes of the state as real total cap­i­tal­ist: “The more pro­duc­tive forces it takes over into its pos­ses­sion, the more it actu­ally becomes a real aggre­gate cap­i­tal­ist, the more cit­i­zens it exploits.” Here Engels reveals a lim­ited under­stand­ing of pri­vate pro­duc­tion, and a ten­dency to equate state plan­ning and monop­oly power with direct social­iza­tion,56 rein­forced by his con­struc­tion of the fun­da­men­tal con­tra­dic­tion and his ten­dency to iden­tify the divi­sion of labor within a fac­tory and the divi­sion of labor in soci­ety. Engels does note that “the trans­for­ma­tion, either into joint-stock com­pa­nies, or into state own­er­ship, does not do away with the cap­i­tal­is­tic nature of the pro­duc­tive forces,”57 but nonethe­less sees an imme­di­ate tran­si­tion to social­ism set­ting in as a result, whereas the con­cepts of monop­oly and state inter­ven­tion remain “eco­nom­i­cally com­pletely unde­ter­mined.”58 Engels thus sug­gests that the work­ers’ move­ment merely has to take over the forms of cor­po­rate book­keep­ing in joint-stock com­pa­nies and the com­pre­hen­sive plan­ning by monop­o­lies devel­oped in cap­i­tal­ism. For Engels, the bour­geoisie has already become obso­lete through the sep­a­ra­tion of own­er­ship and man­age­ment func­tions.59 The “trans­for­ma­tion of the great estab­lish­ments for pro­duc­tion and dis­tri­b­u­tion into joint-stock com­pa­nies and state prop­erty” demon­strates, accord­ing to Engels, “how unnec­es­sary the bour­geoisie are for that pur­pose”, i.e. for man­ag­ing “mod­ern pro­duc­tive forces”: “All the social func­tions of the cap­i­tal­ist are now per­formed by salaried employ­ees. The cap­i­tal­ist has no fur­ther social func­tion than that of pock­et­ing div­i­dends, tear­ing off coupons, and gam­bling on the Stock Exchange, where the dif­fer­ent cap­i­tal­ists despoil one another of their cap­i­tal. At first the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion forces out the work­ers. Now it forces out the cap­i­tal­ists, and reduces them, just as it reduced the work­ers, to the ranks of the sur­plus pop­u­la­tion, although not imme­di­ately into those of the indus­trial reserve army.”60

Review­ing this his­tory of recep­tion (only roughly out­lined here), one could claim that Marx­ism in the form pre­sented here was a rumor about Marx’s the­ory, a rumor that was grate­fully taken up by most crit­ics of “Marx” and merely sup­ple­mented with a minus sign. In fact such an asser­tion – as accu­rate as it may be over­all – makes things too easy, in that it dis­re­gards cer­tain devi­a­tions from the dom­i­nant doc­trine that also under­stood them­selves to be Marxisms, while also regard­ing the above mis­in­ter­pre­ta­tions as com­pletely exter­nal to Marx’s own the­ory, thus exclud­ing the pos­si­bil­ity of any incon­sis­ten­cies or theoretical-ideological ambi­gu­i­ties in Marx’s work. To clar­ify this ques­tion, a glance at the dif­fer­en­ti­ated read­ing of Marx’s texts worked out in the so-called “recon­struc­tion debates” will be useful.

In this respect, tra­di­tional Marx­ism should be under­stood here as an elab­o­ra­tion, sys­tem­ati­za­tion, and assump­tion of dom­i­nance of the ide­o­log­i­cal con­tent of Marx’s work – within the frame­work of a recep­tion by Engels and his epigones. Prac­ti­cal influ­ence was almost exclu­sively allot­ted to these restricted and ide­ol­o­gized inter­pre­ta­tions of Marx’s the­ory, as his­tor­i­cal deter­min­ism or pro­le­tar­ian polit­i­cal economy.

II. West­ern Marxism

The for­ma­tion of a West­ern Marx­ism61 arises from the cri­sis of the social­ist work­ers’ move­ment in the wake of the First World War (the col­lapse of the Sec­ond Inter­na­tional as a result of the pol­icy of defense of the father­land, the defeat of rev­o­lu­tions in Cen­tral and South­ern Europe, the emer­gence of fas­cist forces, etc.). Here it is Georg Lukács’ and Karl Korsch’s texts pub­lished in 1923 which assume a par­a­dig­matic char­ac­ter. Above all Lukács is con­sid­ered the first Marx­ist the­o­rist who at the level of social the­ory and method­ol­ogy called into ques­tion the hith­erto self-evident assump­tion of the com­plete iden­tity of Marx’s and Engels’ the­o­ries. At the cen­ter of his cri­tique stood Engels’ neglect of the subject-object dialec­tic as well as his con­cept of a dialec­tic of nature, to which the fatal­ism of Sec­ond Inter­na­tional Marx­ism was ori­ented. Against this ontol­o­giza­tion of his­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism into a con­tem­pla­tive world­view, Lukács, like West­ern Marx­ism as a whole, under­stands Marx’s approach to be a crit­i­cal rev­o­lu­tion­ary the­ory of social praxis. Against the sci­en­tis­tic talk of “objec­tive laws of devel­op­ment” of social progress, Lukács posits the cri­tique of ide­ol­ogy of rei­fied con­scious­ness, deci­pher­ing the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion as a his­tor­i­cally spe­cific form of social praxis ossi­fied into a “sec­ond nature,” and empha­siz­ing rev­o­lu­tion as a crit­i­cal act of prac­ti­cal sub­jec­tiv­ity. Self-descriptions such as “phi­los­o­phy of praxis” (Gram­sci) or “crit­i­cal the­ory of soci­ety” (Horkheimer) there­fore do not con­sti­tute code words or con­cep­tual equiv­a­lents for offi­cial party doc­trine, but rather empha­size a learn­ing process from which “arises a crit­i­cal, action-oriented cur­rent of thought of Marx­ist her­itage.”62 Although West­ern Marx­ism at first pos­i­tively adopted the activist impulses of the Octo­ber Rev­o­lu­tion, its lead­ing rep­re­sen­ta­tives would quickly come to reject the doc­trine of Lenin­ism, above all its con­tin­u­a­tion of a nat­u­ral­is­tic social the­ory and its false uni­ver­sal­iza­tion of the expe­ri­ence of the Russ­ian Rev­o­lu­tion. Georg Lukács’ cri­tique of Bukharin’s “The­ory of His­tor­i­cal Mate­ri­al­ism” serves as an exam­ple of the for­mer. In his cri­tique, Lukács charges that Bukharin’s the­ory, with its con­cepts of the pri­macy of the devel­op­ment of the forces of pro­duc­tion and the seam­less appli­ca­tion of the meth­ods of nat­ural sci­ence to the study of soci­ety, is fetishis­tic and oblit­er­ates the “qual­i­ta­tive dif­fer­ence” between the two sub­ject areas of nat­ural and social sci­ences, thus acquir­ing “the accent of a false ‘objec­tiv­ity’ and mis­tak­ing the core idea of Marx’s method, namely the ascrip­tion of “all eco­nomic phe­nom­ena to the social rela­tion­ships of human beings to one another.”63

In his Prison Note­books, Gram­sci pro­vided the exem­plary cri­tique of the fix­a­tion of rev­o­lu­tion­ary strat­egy upon the model of the Octo­ber Rev­o­lu­tion. Ini­tially, he had greeted the Octo­ber Rev­o­lu­tion as a “rev­o­lu­tion against Karl Marx’s Cap­i­tal,”64 that is to say as a refu­ta­tion of the allegedly proven impos­si­bil­ity of social­ist rev­o­lu­tion in indus­tri­ally back­wards coun­tries. In an almost rev­o­lu­tion­ary man­ner, he cited the vol­un­taris­tic “social­ist annun­ci­a­tion” as a source of a col­lec­tive social­ist “pop­u­lar will” against a class con­scious­ness mechan­i­cally derived from the econ­omy and the level of its forces of pro­duc­tion. Later, Gram­sci would con­front the Marx­ism of the Third Inter­na­tional with his the­ory of hege­mony, which rejects the “war of maneu­ver” of a frontal attack upon the repres­sive state appa­ra­tus as being a use­less rev­o­lu­tion­ary strat­egy for mod­ern West­ern cap­i­tal­ist soci­eties. Accord­ing to Gram­sci, within these social for­ma­tions “civil soci­ety” is com­posed of a labyrinthine struc­ture of appa­ra­tuses in which pat­terns of thought and behav­ior are gen­er­ated which exhibit an iner­tia that can­not be shaken by grandiose polit­i­cal deeds. The Russ­ian rev­o­lu­tion­ary model is also con­demned to fail­ure in the West because the belief in the uni­ver­sal nature of expe­ri­ence of the Bol­she­viks with a centralist-despotic Tsarism leads to a dis­re­gard for the rel­e­vance of ide­o­log­i­cal social­iza­tion by means of the appa­ra­tuses of civil soci­ety, and their effect: sub­jec­tion in the form of autonomous agency. How­ever, both Lukács and Gram­sci remain loyal to the “exclu­sively pro­le­tar­ian” con­cep­tion of rev­o­lu­tion to the extent that the for­mer, despite his reflec­tions upon rei­fied con­scious­ness, still attrib­utes an epis­te­mo­log­i­cal priv­i­lege to the pro­le­tariat guar­an­teed by its eco­nomic posi­tion, while Gramsci’s strate­gi­cally moti­vated the­ory of civil soci­ety is fix­ated upon the room for maneu­ver of the work­ing class.

With the attempt at a social-psychological explo­ration of the drive/structural foun­da­tions of the repro­duc­tion of an “irra­tional soci­ety,” above all in the form of author­i­tar­ian and anti­se­mitic atti­tudes, the Frank­furt Insti­tute for Social Research, after Max Horkheimer’s assump­tion of its direc­tor­ship in 1931, achieved a level of reflec­tion that other rep­re­sen­ta­tives and cur­rents of West­ern Marx­ism could not match,65 and which gives up on the reas­sur­ing sup­port of an imag­ined class con­scious­ness of the pro­le­tariat. Finally, the empir­i­cal class con­scious­ness of the pro­le­tariat as the only exist­ing class con­scious­ness is sub­jected to analy­sis, while the “irra­tional,” emo­tional dimen­sions of social praxis ignored by other the­o­rists, such as the social dimen­sions of the libid­i­nal, are con­sid­ered. This the­o­ret­i­cal insight into the uncom­pro­mis­ing nature of crit­i­cal the­ory is at the same time an admis­sion of the his­tor­i­cal process of an increas­ing rift between eman­ci­pa­tory the­ory and the per­spec­tive of rev­o­lu­tion­ary praxis. With the prop­a­ga­tion of social­ism in one coun­try, the Bol­she­viza­tion of the West­ern Com­mu­nist Par­ties, and the estab­lish­ment of Marxism-Leninism as the offi­cial ide­ol­ogy of the Third Inter­na­tional after the mid-1920s, there begins the char­ac­ter­is­tic iso­la­tion of the rep­re­sen­ta­tives of West­ern Marx­ism: this cur­rent is left with nei­ther polit­i­cal influ­ence nor (with the pos­si­ble excep­tion of the Frank­furt Insti­tute for Social Research) the insti­tu­tional foun­da­tions for a nor­mal schol­arly praxis. The gen­eral char­ac­ter­is­tics of this Marx­ist for­ma­tion – its sense for the Hegelian legacy and the critical-humanist poten­tial of Marx’s the­ory, the incor­po­ra­tion of con­tem­po­rary “bour­geois” approaches to elu­ci­date the great cri­sis of the work­ers move­ment, the ori­en­ta­tion towards method­ol­ogy, the sen­si­ti­za­tion to social-psychological and cul­tural phe­nom­ena in con­nec­tion with the ques­tion con­cern­ing the rea­sons for the fail­ure of rev­o­lu­tion in “the West”66  –pro­vides the frame­work for a new type of restricted exe­ge­sis of Marx. This is essen­tially char­ac­ter­ized by the neglect of prob­lems of pol­i­tics and state the­ory, a selec­tive recep­tion of Marx’s the­ory of value, and the pre­dom­i­nance of a “silent ortho­doxy” con­cern­ing the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy. Although the first to under­stand the char­ac­ter of cap­i­tal­ist rule the way Marx did – anony­mous, objec­tively medi­ated, and hav­ing a life of its own – the “found­ing doc­u­ment” of West­ern Marx­ism, Lukacs’ His­tory and Class Con­scious­ness, avoids a recon­struc­tion of Marx’s the­ory of cap­i­tal­ism. Instead of an analy­sis of Marx’s dialec­tic of the form of value up to the form of cap­i­tal, which in the the­ory of real sub­sump­tion offers an expla­na­tion of the con­nec­tion – so deci­sive for Lukács – between com­mod­i­fi­ca­tion and the alien­ated struc­ture of the labor process, one finds merely an analo­giz­ing com­bi­na­tion of a value the­ory reduced to the “quan­ti­fy­ing” value-form (due to an ori­en­ta­tion towards Simmel’s cul­tural cri­tique of money) and a diag­no­sis, ori­ented towards Max Weber, of the formal-rational ten­dency of the objec­ti­fi­ca­tion of the labor process and mod­ern law. Until the mid-1960s it seems that no West­ern Marx­ists extended their debate with tra­di­tional inter­pre­ta­tions of Marx into the realm of value the­ory. Some posi­tions go even fur­ther than this silent ortho­doxy, and – with­out hav­ing seri­ously engaged with the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy – con­trast the “human­ist cul­tural critic Marx” with the “econ­o­mist Marx” or even regard a “Marx­ism” with­out a cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy as being pos­si­ble.67

III. The “Neue Marx-Lektüre”

It was first within the frame­work of the “neue Marx-Lektüre” (“New Read­ing of Marx”), which emerged in the mid-1960s, that prob­lems of state the­ory and eco­nomic the­ory once again played a role out­side of Marxism-Leninism. This new wave of recep­tion of Marx’s the­ory was also more or less sit­u­ated out­side of Stal­in­ism and Social Democ­racy. Along­side the new read­ing in West Euro­pean coun­tries, there were iso­lated rudi­ments of a “new read­ing of Marx” occur­ring in East­ern Europe.68 Its gen­e­sis in West Ger­many coin­cided with phe­nom­ena such as the stu­dent move­ment, the first jolts to belief in a per­pet­ual and polit­i­cally man­age­able post-war pros­per­ity, the break­ing up of the anti-communist con­sen­sus in the course of the Viet­nam War, etc., yet remained, despite its rad­i­cal eman­ci­pa­tory claims, con­fined largely to acad­e­mia. Here, we dis­tin­guish between this “new read­ing of Marx” in a broader sense69, and one more nar­rowly defined.70 Whereas the for­mer was an inter­na­tional phe­nom­e­non, the lat­ter was con­fined pri­mar­ily to West Ger­many. If the for­mer still remained pre­dom­i­nantly trapped within Engel­sian dogma with regard to the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy, the lat­ter fore­grounded the revi­sion of pre­vi­ous his­tori­cist or empiri­cist inter­pre­ta­tions of Marx’s form analy­sis. In terms of con­tent, a three­fold aban­don­ment of cen­tral topoi of tra­di­tional Marx­ism was con­sum­mated in the main threads of the debate, them­selves con­tra­dic­tory and in no way shared by all par­tic­i­pants: a move away from a sub­stan­tial­ist the­ory of value71; aban­don­ment of manipulative-instrumental con­cep­tions of the state72; and a move away from labor movement-centric inter­pre­ta­tions of the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy, or inter­pre­ta­tions based on a “labor-ontological” rev­o­lu­tion­ary the­ory (or even upon rev­o­lu­tion­ary the­ory as such).73 This new read­ing artic­u­lates its the­o­ret­i­cal efforts in the form of a recon­struc­tion of Marx’s theory.

With regard to the cri­tique of econ­omy, a crys­tal­liza­tion of cen­tral ques­tions and research tasks occurred within the frame­work of the 1967 col­lo­quium “100 Jahre ‘Kap­i­tal.’”74 A rein­ter­pre­ta­tion of Marx’s cri­tique was envi­sioned from the method­olog­i­cal per­spec­tive of social the­ory: the ques­tion as to the orig­i­nal object of Cap­i­tal(eco­nomic form-determination), the par­tic­u­lar­ity of sci­en­tific pre­sen­ta­tion (the dialec­tic of the forms of value), as well as the con­nec­tion between the three vol­umes (“cap­i­tal in gen­eral – many cap­i­tals”) are posed anew, as dis­tinct from quan­ti­ta­tive approaches, and with a par­tic­u­lar empha­sis upon the sig­nif­i­cance of the Grun­drisse. Within the field of the con­flict between “crit­i­cal” and “struc­tural” Marxisms, tran­si­tional moments of flight from exist­ing method­olog­i­cal tra­di­tions arise, oblique to the clas­si­cal points of con­flict75: both struc­tural­ist anti-historicism as well as Hegelian fig­ures of thought (“progressive-regressive method,” “return to the foun­da­tion”) play an impor­tant role in this.

Ini­tially with a lot of “ifs and buts”76, and on some points remain­ing within the chan­nels of tra­di­tional Marx­ism, the New Read­ing of Marx acquired more clearly defined con­tours over the course of the 1970s.

Tra­di­tional read­ings of Marx’s theory
Clas­si­cal Assump­tion of the Marx­ism of the 2nd and 3rd Internationals Marx = Engels (uni­fied par­a­digm, coher­ent argu­men­ta­tion, closed “worldview”)
Lev­els of the critical-reconstructive reading
Level 1: e.g. Back­haus (Mate­ri­alien parts 1 and 2) Engels → exo­teric vs.
Marx → esoteric
Level 2: e.g. Althusser (Read­ing Cap­i­tal); A. Schmidt; Back­haus (Mate­ri­alien) Marx → exo­teric meta-discourse vs.
Marx → eso­teric real analysis
Level 3: e.g. Back­haus (Mate­ri­alien parts 3 and 4); Hein­rich (Sci­ence of Value) Marx → exoteric/esoteric meta-discourse
Marx → exoteric/esoteric real analysis

Against the clas­si­cal myth of the com­plete equal­ity between the par­a­digms of Marx and Engels, with regard to both his­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism and the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy, Engels’ com­men­taries were crit­i­cized as largely inad­e­quate to Marx’s work and remain­ing at a purely “exo­teric” level that per­pet­u­ated tra­di­tional par­a­digms. Thus, in 1974 Hans-Georg Back­haus empha­sized with regard to value the­ory that the cri­tique was aimed “at an inter­pre­ta­tive premise which until recently was con­sid­ered one of the few uncon­tested ele­ments of the Marx­ist lit­er­a­ture, and which struc­tured the recep­tion of Marx’s value the­ory with­out being chal­lenged: the mis­in­ter­pre­ta­tion, touched off by Engels, of the first three chap­ters of Cap­i­tal as a value and money the­ory of what Engels called ‘sim­ple com­mod­ity pro­duc­tion.’”77 Back­haus assumes that “pro­ceed­ing from this fun­da­men­tal error, Marx­ist value the­ory nec­es­sar­ily inhib­ited the recep­tion of Marx’s value the­ory.”78 If there­fore at this level an ini­tial dis­tinc­tion is made between a Marx­ist the­ory and Marx’s the­ory, a prob­lema­ti­za­tion of Marx’s meta-theoretical self-understanding also occurs early on. Louis Althusser had already affirmed, with the aid of a “symp­to­matic” read­ing directed against a subject-centric inten­tion­al­ist hermeneu­tic, that Marx’s work rep­re­sents a sci­en­tific rev­o­lu­tion in the the­o­ret­i­cal praxis of the analy­sis of cap­i­tal­ism, which at the meta-theoretical level is super­im­posed upon by a dis­course inad­e­quate to this prob­lem­atic. Althusser defines the tasks of a recon­struc­tion as the removal of the inad­e­quate meta-discourse and the trans­for­ma­tion of its dom­i­nant metaphors, which he reads as symp­toms for the absence of an ade­quate self-reflection of the real pro­ce­dure of the analy­sis of cap­i­tal, into con­cepts.79 As dis­tinct from Althusser and his dual­ist con­cep­tion of the rela­tion­ship between the real object and the object of knowl­edge80, this issue is usu­ally for­mu­lated in the recon­struc­tion debate within the the­o­ret­i­cal frame­work of a Marx­ian cri­tique of ide­ol­ogy: Marx dis­tin­guishes between “eso­teric” and “exo­teric” lev­els in the works of clas­si­cal polit­i­cal econ­omy. If the for­mer con­tains insights into the social con­text of medi­a­tion of the bour­geois mode of pro­duc­tion, the lat­ter is con­tent with an unmedi­ated descrip­tion and sys­tem­ati­za­tion of the objec­tive forms of thought of the every­day con­scious­ness of social actors, remain­ing trapped in the rei­fied illu­sion of the imme­di­acy of phe­nom­ena which are in fact socially medi­ated. So the “exo­teric” argu­men­ta­tion can­not be traced back psy­cho­log­i­cally to sub­jec­tive defi­cien­cies or even con­scious attempts at decep­tion on the part of the­o­rists. It results from a deter­mi­nate form of thought which is the sys­tem­atic and ini­tially invol­un­tary prod­uct of the forms of social inter­course of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion. The recon­struc­tion debate would now apply the esoteric/exoteric dis­tinc­tion to Marx’s work itself.

Ulti­mately, even in the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy and in his­tor­i­cal mate­ri­al­ism – that is to say in the the­o­ret­i­cal praxis regarded at the pre­vi­ous stage of recon­struc­tion as an intact “eso­teric” layer – “exo­teric” con­tent and con­cep­tual ambiva­lence “between sci­en­tific rev­o­lu­tion and clas­si­cal tra­di­tion”81 are man­i­fest. The doc­trine of the invi­o­la­bil­ity of the pre­sen­ta­tion of the cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy in Cap­i­tal is finally dis­carded. In place of the leg­end of a lin­ear pro­gres­sion of knowl­edge on Marx’s part, there appeared the recog­ni­tion of a com­plex coex­is­tence and inter­pen­e­tra­tion of progress and regres­sion in the method of pre­sen­ta­tion and the state of research of Marx’s cri­tique of econ­omy. Ulti­mately, the increased pop­u­lar­iza­tion of the pre­sen­ta­tion of the analy­sis of the forms of value from the Grun­drisse to the sec­ond edi­tion of Cap­i­tal was pointed out. This pop­u­lar­iza­tion, to the extent that it increas­ingly con­cealed the form-genetic method, offered points of ref­er­ence to his­tori­cist and sub­stan­tial­ist read­ings.82

IV. Learn­ing Processes within Marxism

Since there is not enough space within the frame­work of this text to elu­ci­date even approx­i­mately the aspects of a sci­en­tific rev­o­lu­tion – inter­nal learn­ing processes, but also regres­sions to tra­di­tional eco­nomic and historical-philosophical posi­tions in Marx’s work – I will attempt to briefly men­tion some of the points arrived at in the above-mentioned learn­ing processes within Marxism.

Marx’s the­ory does not affirm some kind of auto­matic lib­er­a­tion; rather, it should be under­stood as the the­o­ret­i­cal instance of a body of work, medi­ated by analy­sis and cri­tique, con­tribut­ing to the lib­er­a­tion from the automa­tism of an irra­tional mode of social­iza­tion. Marx’s asser­tion that he grasps the devel­op­ment of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion as “a process of nat­ural his­tory,”83 often cited by both Marx­ists and anti-Marxists as proof either of the high­est sci­en­tific sta­tus of Marx’s work or of unsci­en­tific prophecy, should be under­stood as a crit­i­cal state­ment. “Nature” or “nat­u­ral­ness” are neg­a­tively deter­mined cat­e­gories for a social sys­tem that, on the basis of its con­sti­tu­tion by the pri­vate divi­sion of labor, asserts itself with regard to social actors as a relent­less machine using up abstract labor, as a “des­tiny of value” beyond all col­lec­tive and indi­vid­ual con­trol and yet repro­duc­ing itself by means of their activity.

Marx’s the­ory is “a uni­fied crit­i­cal judg­ment on pre­vi­ous his­tory, to the effect that men have allowed them­selves to be degraded into objects of the blind and mechan­i­cal process of its eco­nomic devel­op­ment.”84 While Marx does suc­cumb to a his­tor­i­cal opti­mism that often tips over into a phi­los­o­phy of his­tory in the declam­a­tory sec­tions of his works, this is fun­da­men­tally con­tra­dicted by his sci­en­tific cri­tique of philoso­phies of his­tory and polit­i­cal econ­omy.85 But it is pre­cisely from these cliches that the Marx­ism of the Sec­ond and Third Inter­na­tion­als, as well as the more edu­cated among those who dis­dain Marx, paste together an abstruse sys­tem of iron his­tor­i­cal neces­si­ties, up to and includ­ing a “law of the sequence of social for­ma­tions” which estab­lishes the “gen­eral his­tor­i­cally nec­es­sary ten­dency of the progress of the human species.”86

The cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy, which in the form of Marx’s late works “does not with­stand com­par­i­son with the imma­nent claim of the pro­gram­matic dec­la­ra­tion inThe Ger­man Ide­ol­ogy,”87 namely of pre­sent­ing the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion in its total­ity, can be pre­sented as a process of four cri­tiques: 1) the cri­tique of bour­geois soci­ety and its destruc­tive “nat­ural” forms of devel­op­ment, against the back­ground of the real, objec­tive pos­si­bil­ity it gen­er­ates of its own eman­ci­pa­tory tran­scen­dence, 2) the cri­tique of the fetishized and back­ward every­day con­scious­ness of social actors sys­tem­at­i­cally gen­er­ated by these social rela­tions, 3) the cri­tique of the entire the­o­ret­i­cal field of polit­i­cal econ­omy88, which uncrit­i­cally sys­tem­atizes these com­mon per­cep­tions, and 4) the cri­tique of utopian social crit­i­cism, which either con­fronts the sys­tem of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion with a model of social lib­er­a­tion, or pre­sumes to bring iso­lated eco­nomic forms to bear against the sys­tem as a whole by means of reforms.89 The cri­tique is there­fore not imma­nent in the sense that it would affirm the deter­mi­na­tions of exchange, bour­geois ideals, pro­le­tar­ian demands for rights, or indus­trial pro­duc­tion (which is sub­sumed to cap­i­tal) against cap­i­tal­ism as a whole.

The method of the cri­tique of econ­omy can be described as the “devel­op­ment” or “analy­sis of forms.” It aims to grasp the spe­cific social­ity of his­tor­i­cally dis­tinct modes of pro­duc­tion. Whereas “bour­geois” approaches con­duct at best a sci­ence of the repro­duc­tion of soci­ety within spe­cific eco­nomic and polit­i­cal forms, a cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy must be con­ceived of as a sci­ence of these forms.90 Polit­i­cal econ­omy oper­ates at the level of already con­sti­tuted eco­nomic objects, takes them empir­i­cally as a given, or can only jus­tify their exis­tence in a cir­cu­lar man­ner, with­out con­cep­tu­ally pen­e­trat­ing the sys­tem­atic process of their con­sti­tu­tion. It suc­cumbs to the self-mystification of the cap­i­tal­ist world of objects as a world of nat­ural forms91, thus depriv­ing humans of the abil­ity to con­fig­ure and alter their fun­da­men­tal structures.

In con­trast, form-analysis devel­ops these forms (such as value, money, cap­i­tal, but also law and the state) from the con­tra­dic­tory con­di­tions of the social con­sti­tu­tion of labor, “clar­i­fies them, grasps their essence and neces­sity.”92 Form devel­op­ment is not to be under­stood as the retrac­ing of the his­tor­i­cal devel­op­ment of the object, but rather the con­cep­tual deci­pher­ing of the imma­nent struc­tural rela­tion­ships of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion. It unscram­bles the appar­ently inde­pen­dent, appar­ently objec­tively grounded forms of social wealth and the polit­i­cal com­pul­sion of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion as his­tor­i­cally spe­cific and there­fore – albeit in no way arbi­trar­ily or in a piece­meal man­ner – as change­able forms of praxis.

Tra­di­tional as well as West­ern Marx­ism had com­pletely ignored the rev­o­lu­tion­ary sci­en­tific poten­tial of Marx’s approach, his the­ory of the mon­e­tary con­sti­tu­tion of value. Above all, the neue Marx-Lektüre crit­i­cized the empiricist-historicist mis­in­ter­pre­ta­tion of the method of pre­sen­ta­tion that started with Engels, and the “pre­mon­e­tary” inter­pre­ta­tion of the the­ory of value in Cap­i­tal, but also ambiva­lences in Marx’s work itself and the pop­u­lar­iza­tion of his method, which meant “for­go­ing a sys­tem­atic elab­o­ra­tion of fun­da­men­tal ideas of value the­ory and method­ol­ogy.”93 Engels and Tra­di­tional Marx­ism inter­preted dif­fer­ent lev­els of abstrac­tion of the pre­sen­ta­tion of the laws of the cap­i­tal­ist mode of pro­duc­tion in Cap­i­tal as empir­i­cally coequal lev­els of a model of his­tor­i­cally dis­tinct modes of pro­duc­tion. Thus cat­e­gories such as abstract labor, value, and the ele­men­tary form of value were rein­ter­preted in an empiri­cist way, and the con­nec­tion between com­mod­ity, money, and cap­i­tal – con­sid­ered essen­tial by Marx – was trans­formed into a coin­ci­dence. Marx­ism thus oper­ated on a method­olog­i­cal and value-theoretical ter­rain that Marx had crit­i­cized with regard to clas­si­cal eco­nom­ics. How­ever, Marx’s cri­tique of polit­i­cal econ­omy is dis­tinct from an alter­na­tive polit­i­cal econ­omy in pri­mar­ily two respects: in the first instance it is not the the­ory of surplus-value, but rather the form the­ory of labor that dis­tin­guishes Marx from clas­si­cal polit­i­cal econ­omy. Marx crit­i­cizes the way polit­i­cal econ­omy unre­flec­tively pre­sup­poses the form of “value,” never ques­tion­ing its gen­e­sis, unable to grasp labor that takes the form of value as a his­tor­i­cally spe­cific social form (the ques­tion is not raised as to “why labour is rep­re­sented by the value of its prod­uct”94). Polit­i­cal econ­omy there­fore oper­ates fun­da­men­tally within the field of fetishis­tic forms. More­over, Marx crit­i­cizes the pre­mon­e­tary char­ac­ter of its value the­ory, since it “treat[s] the form of value as a thing of no impor­tance, as hav­ing no con­nec­tion with the inher­ent nature of com­modi­ties,”95 mean­ing it does not dis­tin­guish between intrin­sic and exter­nal mea­sure of value as cat­e­gories exist­ing at two dif­fer­ent lev­els of the­o­ret­i­cal abstrac­tion, and does not grasp the neces­sity of the money-form for the exchange of com­modi­ties. Money is under­stood as a purely tech­ni­cal instru­ment which for rea­sons of con­ve­nience takes the place of exchange on the basis of cal­cu­la­tions of labor-time mag­ni­tudes. In Marx’s work, on the other hand, money is devel­oped as a nec­es­sary moment in the process of com­mod­ity exchange. With­out a gen­eral form of value, val­ues can­not rep­re­sent value for each other, and would be reduced to the sta­tus of prod­ucts. One must there­fore pro­ceed from the “equip­ri­mor­dial” con­sti­tu­tion of abstract labor as a log­i­cally prior imma­nent mea­sure of value, and money as the exter­nal mea­sure of value. In this sense, Marx speaks of the sub­stance of value as a result obtained in exchange which fur­ther­more first acquires an intertem­po­ral exis­tence as cap­i­tal. In con­trast to the empiri­cism and ahis­tori­cism of polit­i­cal econ­omy, Marx’s approach thus reveals itself to be a per­cep­tion of essence in the sense of the recon­struc­tion of a struc­ture and sys­tem of agency which is empir­i­cally not imme­di­ately per­ceiv­able – by means of the elab­o­ra­tion of a non-empirical the­o­ret­i­cal level which first makes pos­si­ble the expla­na­tion of empir­i­cal forms of appear­ance, such as money. Marx fol­lows “a prin­ci­ple of the devel­op­ment of eco­nomic cat­e­gories by dis­tin­guish­ing between dif­fer­ent lev­els of abstrac­tion.”96 Cat­e­gories such as abstract labor or value there­fore have no imme­di­ate empir­i­cal ref­er­ents. The sequence of the cat­e­gories of com­mod­ity and money is not to be under­stood as a his­tor­i­cal sequence of inde­pen­dently exist­ing cir­cum­stances, but rather as a con­cep­tual analysis.

Overview of the Marxisms

Impor­tant Theorists Cen­tral Ref­er­ence Texts of Marx/Engels Core Con­cept: Marx’s The­ory as…
Tra­di­tional Marx­ism [1878ff.] [F. Engels], K. Kaut­sky, E. Bern­stein, Lafar­gue, F. Mehring, A. Bebel, G. Plekhanov, etc.(= 1st Gen­er­a­tion); V.I. Lenin, L. Trotsky, R. Luxemburg, N. Bukharin, M. Adler, R. Hil­fer­d­ing (= 2nd Generation) Claim: Doc­trine of the mate­ri­al­ist con­cep­tion of his­tory as the cen­ter of the col­lab­o­ra­tive works of Marx and EngelsEngels: Anti-DühringLud­wig Feuer­bach, “Review of A Con­tri­bu­tion to the Cri­tique of Polit­i­cal Econ­omy (1859) etc.Marx: Cap­i­tal Vol. 1 – Chap­ter 32, “Pref­ace” to Cri­tique (1859), Man­i­festo (M/E) Closed, coher­ent pro­le­tar­ian world­view and doc­trine of the evo­lu­tion of nature and his­tory (“becom­ing and pass­ing away”)
West­ern Marx­ism [1923ff.] G. Lukács, K. Korsch, E. Bloch, H. Lefeb­vre, Frank­furt School, A. Gram­sci, K. Kosik, Yugoslav Praxis-Group (G. Petrovic, P. Vran­icki, etc.), Budapest School (A. Heller, G. Markus, etc.), L. Kofler, J.-P. Sartre Claim: Human­ist early work as inter­pre­ta­tive frame­work for the “scientific” later worksMarx: “The­ses on Feuer­bach,” 1844 Man­u­scripts, The Ger­man Ide­ol­ogy(M/E) Critical-revolutionary the­ory of social praxis (“sub­jec­tive medi­a­tion of the object”)
neue Marx-Lektüre [1965ff.] [Pre­de­ces­sors: I.I. Rubin, E. Paschuka­nis] H.G. Back­haus, H. Reichelt, D. Wolf, H.D. Kittsteiner, M. Hein­rich, SOST, Projekt Klassenanalyse/PEM, S. Breuer, State-Derivation Debate (B. Blanke, D. Läpple, MG, J. Hirsch, W. Müller/ Ch. Neusüß, N. Kost­ede, etc.) Claim: appre­hend­ing the whole Marx, or later works as inter­pre­ta­tive frame­work for the early worksMarx:Grun­drisseCap­i­tal Vol. I first edi­tion,Urtext, “Results of the Imme­di­ate Process of Production” Deci­pher­ing and Cri­tique of the Forms of cap­i­tal­ist social­iza­tion by means of logical-systematic method of pre­sen­ta­tions (“form-development and critique”)

– Trans­lated by Alexan­der Locascio

Image thanks to f2b1610.

  1. Karl Kaut­sky, quoted in Gareth Sted­man Jones, “Engels und die Geschichte des Marx­is­mus,” in Klassen, Poli­tik, Sprache. Für eine the­o­rieori­en­tierte Sozialgeschichte (Mün­ster: West­fälis­ches Dampfboot,1988), 234n; V.I. Lenin, “The Three Sources and Three Com­po­nent Parts of Marx­ism.” All Eng­lish quo­ta­tions from Marx, Engels, Lenin, and Kaut­sky taken from the ver­sions avail­able at 
  2. Fred­er­ick Engels, “Dialec­tics” in Dialec­tics of Nature
  3. Engels, “Intro­duc­tion” in Anti-Dühring
  4. Engels, “Hegel” in Lud­wig Feuer­bach and the End of Ger­man Clas­si­cal Phi­los­o­phy
  5. Ibid. 
  6. Engels, “Marx” in Lud­wig Feuer­bach. 
  7. Karl Marx, “The­ses on Feuer­bach.” 
  8. Engels, “Notes and Frag­ments” in Dialec­tics of Nature
  9. Above all in Mate­ri­al­ism and Empiri­o­crit­i­cism, styl­ized by Marxism-Leninism as the clas­si­cal text­book of dialec­ti­cal mate­ri­al­ism along­side Anti-Dühring. Here, Marx­ism becomes an ide­ol­ogy in the strict Marx­ian sense: a sys­tem­iza­tion of the forms of thought of a rei­fied com­mon sense. Con­cern­ing the political-pragamatical back­ground of the text, usu­ally dis­re­garded in ML, see Johannes Busch-Weßlau, Der Marx­is­mus und die Legit­i­ma­tion poli­tis­cher Macht (Frank­furt: Cam­pus Verl, 1990), 30. 
  10. Falko Schmieder points to the a pri­ori role of the medium of pho­tog­ra­phy as a foun­da­tion of this naive real­ism in phi­los­o­phy, as well as the fun­da­men­tal com­mon­al­i­ties between Engels, Lenin, and Feuer­bach; Lud­wig Feuer­bach und der Ein­gang der klas­sis­chen Fotografie. Zum Ver­hält­nis von anthro­pol­o­gis­chem und His­torischem Mate­ri­al­is­mus(Berlin: PHILO-Verlag, 2004), 213. 
  11. Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Waren­form und Denk­form (Frank­furt: Suhrkamp, 1978),114. 
  12. Engels, “Marx” in Lud­wig Feuer­bach
  13. Marx, “The­ses on Feuer­bach.” 
  14. Engels, “Mate­ri­al­ism” in Lud­wig Feuer­bach. 
  15. For more on this, see the study of Hans-Josef Stein­berg [1967], Sozial­is­mus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie. Zur Ide­olo­gie der Partei vor dem 1. Weltkrieg (Berlin-Bonn: 1979), above all 45, 63. Approaches toward a social his­tor­i­cal expla­na­tion are offered by idem, 145-150; Dieter Groh, Neg­a­tive Inte­gra­tion und rev­o­lu­tionärer Atten­tismus. Die deutsche Sozialdemokratie am Vor­abend des Ersten Weltkrieges (Frank­furt: Ull­stein Taschen­buchvlg, 1974), 58-63; Oskar Negt, “Marx­is­mus als Legit­i­ma­tion­swis­senschaft,” in N. Bucharin/A. Deborin – Kon­tro­ver­sen über dialek­tis­chen und mech­a­nis­tis­chen Mate­ri­al­is­mus (Frank­furt: Suhrkamp, 1974); Anto­nio Gram­sci, Philoso­phie der Praxis. Eine Auswahl(Frank­furt: S Fis­cher, 1967),1386. 
  16. For a cri­tique, see Alexan­drine Mohl, Vere­len­dung und Rev­o­lu­tion. Oder: Das Elend des Objek­tivis­mus. Zugle­ich ein Beitrag zur Marxrezep­tion in der deutschen Sozialdemokratie(Frank­furt 1978); Rolf Peter Sieferle, Die Rev­o­lu­tion in der The­o­rie von Karl Marx (Berlin: Ull­stein, 1979); Ingo Elbe, “‘Umwälzungsmo­mente der alten Gesellschaft’ – Aspekte der Rev­o­lu­tion­s­the­o­rie und ihrer Kri­tik bei Marx,” 2002. 
  17. Ernesto Laclau and Chan­tal Mouffe point out the Darwinist-Hegelian char­ac­ter of this con­cep­tion: “Dar­win­ism alone does not offer ‘guar­an­tees for the future,’ since nat­ural selec­tion does not oper­ate in a direc­tion pre­de­ter­mined from the begin­ning. Only if a Hegelian type of tele­ol­ogy is added to Dar­win­ism – which is totally incom­pat­i­ble with it – can an evo­lu­tion­ary process be pre­sented as a guar­an­tee of future tran­si­tions”; Hege­mony and Social­ist Strat­egy (New York: Verso, 2001), 20. 
  18. For more on this, in an instruc­tive man­ner, see Heinz Dieter Kittsteiner, “Bewusst­seins­bil­dung, Parteilichkeit, dialek­tis­cher und his­torischer Mate­ri­al­is­mus. Zu eini­gen Kat­e­gorien der marxistisch-leninistischen Geschichtsmethod­olo­gie,” Inter­na­tionale Wis­senschaftliche Kor­re­spon­denz zur Geschichte der deutschen Arbeit­er­be­we­gung. Jg. 10, 1974. 
  19. See Groh, Neg­a­tive Inte­gra­tion, 36. 
  20. Kaut­sky, quoted in Stein­berg, Sozial­is­mus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie, 61. See alsoEthics and the Mate­ri­al­ist Con­cep­tion Of His­tory. Accord­ing to Kaut­sky, the prospects for free­dom and human­ity are not “mere expec­ta­tions of con­di­tions which only ought to come, which we sim­ply wish and will, but out­looks at con­di­tions which must come, which are nec­es­sary.” Kaut­sky defends him­self against inter­pre­ta­tions of neces­sity “in the fatal­ist sense, that a higher power will present them to us of itself,” but assumes an irre­sistible imma­nent historical-economic com­pul­sion toward rev­o­lu­tion, whereby the imma­nent com­pul­sive laws of cap­i­tal­ism and the for­ma­tion of the pro­le­tariat as a suc­cess­ful rev­o­lu­tion­ary sub­ject play the same role: “unavoid­able in the sense, that the […] cap­i­tal­ists in their desire for profit [!] rev­o­lu­tion­ize the whole eco­nomic life, as it is also inevitable that the work­ers aim for shorter hours of labor and higher wages, that they orga­nize them­selves, that they fight the cap­i­tal­ist class and its state, as it is inevitable that they aim for the con­quest of polit­i­cal power and the over­throw of cap­i­tal­ist rule. Social­ism is inevitable because the class strug­gle and the vic­tory of the pro­le­tariat is inevitable.” 
  21. Lenin, “Three Sources.” 
  22. Lenin, Karl Marx: A Brief Bio­graph­i­cal Sketch With an Expo­si­tion of Marx­ism
  23. On the para­doxes of this com­bi­na­tion of vol­un­tarism and deter­min­ism, see Charles Tay­lor,Hegel (Cam­bridge: Cam­bridge Uni­ver­sity Press, 1977). 
  24. It is pre­cisely West­ern Marx­ism that – against Marxism-Leninism – empha­sizes the non-ontological char­ac­ter of Marx’s mate­ri­al­ism; see Max Horkheimer, “Tra­di­tional and Crit­i­cal The­ory” in Crit­i­cal The­ory: Selected Essays (New York: Con­tin­uum, 1972), as well as Alfred Schmidt, The Con­cept of Nature in Marx (New York: Verso, 2014). Stalin deter­mines the com­po­nents of Marx’s the­ory as fol­lows: Dialek­tik: a uni­ver­sal logic of devel­op­ment empha­siz­ing dis­con­ti­nu­ity, which teaches that every­thing can be con­ceived of as in a state of becom­ing and decay­ing; Mate­ri­al­ism: a con­tem­pla­tive ontol­ogy which teaches that con­scious­ness is merely a reflec­tion of a nature exist­ing inde­pen­dent and out­side of con­scious­ness; His­tor­i­cal Mate­ri­al­ism: the appli­ca­tion of dialec­ti­cal mate­ri­al­ism to his­tory; uni­ver­sal his­tor­i­cal laws are class strug­gle, the dialec­tic between forces of pro­duc­tion and rela­tions of pro­duc­tion, rooted in the pri­macy of the devel­op­ment of the forces of pro­duc­tion (casua suicon­cept of forces of pro­duc­tion), and ulti­mately the law of progress of suc­ces­sive social for­ma­tions. 
  25. Engels, “Karl Marx: Cri­tique of Polit­i­cal Econ­omy. Review by Fred­er­ick Engels.” 
  26. Ibid. 
  27. Ibid. 
  28. Kaut­sky [1886], Karl Marx’ ökonomis­che Lehren. Gemein­ver­ständlich dargestellt und erläutert von Karl Kaut­sky, 21. (Berlin: 1922), viii. 
  29. Kaut­sky, quoted in Rolf Hecker, “Ein­fache Waren­pro­duk­tion,” 1997. 
  30. Rudolf Hil­fer­d­ing, Böhm-Bawerk’s Crit­i­cism of Marx
  31. M.M. Rosen­tal [1955], Die dialek­tis­che Meth­ode der poli­tis­chen Ökonomie von Karl Marx(Berlin: Dietz, 1973). 
  32. See Ernest Man­del, Marx­ist Eco­nomic The­ory (New York: Monthly Review Press: 1970). 
  33. “This makes clear, of course, why in the begin­ning of his first book Marx pro­ceeds from the sim­ple pro­duc­tion of com­modi­ties as the his­tor­i­cal premise, ulti­mately to arrive from this basis to cap­i­tal – why he pro­ceeds from the sim­ple com­mod­ity instead of a log­i­cally and his­tor­i­cally sec­ondary form – from an already cap­i­tal­is­ti­cally mod­i­fied com­mod­ity.” Engels, “Pref­ace” in Karl Marx, Cap­i­tal, Vol­ume 3. 
  34. Ibid. This inter­pre­ta­tion of the analy­sis of the form of value is also adopted by Kaut­sky, inThe Eco­nomic Doc­trines of Karl Marx
  35. That is to say, the law of value dis­cussed by Marx. See Engels’ “Sup­ple­ment” to vol­ume 3. 
  36. Ibid 
  37. Ibid. 
  38. “Or is it believed that the peas­ant and the arti­san were so stu­pid as to give up the prod­uct of 10 hours’ labor of one per­son for that of a sin­gle hours’ labor of another?”; and who­ever does so learns “only through mis­takes.” Ibid. 
  39. Ibid. 
  40. In con­trast, see Marx’s cri­tique of the notion of labor-money, or the notion of a pre-monetary com­mod­ity exchange in A Con­tri­bu­tion to the Cri­tique of Polit­i­cal Econ­omy and in the Grun­drisse
  41. See foot­note 33 in chap­ter one of Cap­i­tal, Vol­ume 1. 
  42. For Marx’s view, see for exam­ple: “Adam Smith con­stantly con­fuses the deter­mi­na­tion of the value of com­modi­ties by the labour-time con­tained in them with the deter­mi­na­tion of their value by the value of labour; he is often incon­sis­tent in the details of his expo­si­tion and he mis­takes the objec­tive equal­i­sa­tion of unequal quan­ti­ties of labour forcibly brought about by the social process for the sub­jec­tive equal­ity of the labours of indi­vid­u­als”; A Con­tri­bu­tion to the Cri­tique of Polit­i­cal Econ­omy.  
  43. Accord­ing to Marxism-Leninism, “value func­tions as an instru­ment of the planned admin­is­tra­tion of the social­ist processes of pro­duc­tion and repro­duc­tion, accord­ing to the prin­ci­ples of book­keep­ing and con­trol of the mass of labor and of con­sump­tion. Cor­re­spond­ingly, the rela­tion of value is con­sciously imple­mented”; Wolf­gang Peter Eich­horn, “Wert” in G. Klaus and M. Buhr, ed. Philosophis­ches Wörter­buch, Bd. 2 (Frank­furt: Suhrkamp, 1985), 1291. Within this frame­work, social­ism con­sists “merely in the rev­o­lu­tion­ized way of cal­cu­lat­ing the same social deter­mi­na­tion of the prod­ucts of human labor as exists in the cap­i­tal­ist com­mod­ity econ­omy,” as Ste­fan Gri­gat crit­i­cally notes; “Kri­tik und Utopie,” Weg und Ziel, 4 (1997): 20. Thus, allegedly Marx­ian com­mu­nism degen­er­ates into a sort of Proud­hon­ian sys­tem of labor notes, as Diethard Behrens and Kor­nelia Hafner also observe: “all hith­erto exist­ing con­cep­tions of the tran­si­tion to social­ism resort to mod­els of imme­di­ate cal­cu­la­tion of labor-value and util­ity”; “Auf der Suche nach dem wahren Sozial­is­mus. Von der Kri­tik des Proud­hon­is­mus über die rus­sis­che Mod­ernisierungs­dik­tatur zum real­sozial­is­tis­chen Etiket­ten­schwindel” in Anton Pan­nekoek, Marx­is­tis­cher Antilenin­is­mus (Freiburg, 1991), 226. See here also Michael Hein­rich, Die Wis­senschaft vom Wert. Die Marxsche Kri­tik der poli­tis­chen Ökonomie zwis­chen wis­senschaftlicher Rev­o­lu­tion und klas­sis­cher Tra­di­tion (Mün­ster: West­fälis­ches Dampf­boot, 1999), 385-392; and Kittsteiner, “Bewusst­seins­bil­dung.” 
  44. For exam­ple, Engels, “Marx” in Lud­wig Feuer­bach. 
  45. Ibid. 
  46. Ibid. 
  47. Ibid, trans­la­tion mod­i­fied. 
  48. Gert Schäfer, “Einige Prob­leme des Ver­hält­nisses von ‘ökonomis­cher’ und ‘poli­tis­cher’ Herrschaft,” in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels – Staat­s­the­o­rie. Mate­ri­alien zur Rekon­struk­tion der marx­is­tis­chen Staat­s­the­o­rie (Berlin: Ull­stein, 1974). 
  49. Com­pare Pashuka­nis, The Gen­eral The­ory of Law and Marx­ism: “why is the appa­ra­tus of state coer­cion cre­ated not as a pri­vate appa­ra­tus of the rul­ing class, but dis­tinct from the lat­ter in the form of an imper­sonal appa­ra­tus of pub­lic power dis­tinct from soci­ety?” 
  50. Engels, “Bar­barism and Civ­i­liza­tion” in The Ori­gin of the Fam­ily, Pri­vate Prop­erty, and the State. No won­der, then, that Lenin refers affir­ma­tively to this “expla­na­tion,” with its the­ory of agents and influ­ence. 
  51. Engels, Anti-Dühring. [Translator’s Note: The offi­cial trans­la­tion of “ideeller Gesamtkap­i­tal­ist” in the Marx-Engels Col­lected Works ren­ders this unsat­is­fac­to­rily as “the ideal per­son­i­fi­ca­tion of the total national cap­i­tal,” when in fact “ideal total cap­i­tal­ist” is more accu­rate.] 
  52. Johannes Busch-Weßlau, Der Marx­is­mus und die Legit­i­ma­tion poli­tis­cher Macht, Frank­furt, Campus-Verlag, 1990). 
  53. Engels, Anti-Dühring
  54. Hans Hol­ger Paul, Marx, Engels und die Impe­ri­al­is­mus­the­o­rie der 2. Inter­na­tionale (Ham­burg, 1978). 
  55. Engels, “A Cri­tique of the Draft Social-Democratic Pro­gram of 1891.” 
  56. Schäfer, “Einige Prob­leme,” cxxxi.  
  57. Engels, Anti-Dühring
  58. Schäfer, “Einige Prob­leme,” cxxxiv. 
  59. This old chest­nut will later be pre­sented by Wolf­gang Pohrt and oth­ers as a deep insight about “late cap­i­tal­ism.” 
  60. Engels, Anti-Dühring
  61. The term was prob­a­bly first used in a Lenin­ist polemic against Lukács’ His­tory and Class Con­scious­ness (see Rudolf Walther, “Marx­is­mus” in O. Brun­ner, ed., Geschichtliche Grund­be­griffe. His­torisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutsch­land, Bd. 3, [Stuttgart: E. Klett, 1982], 968), but did not achieve greater sig­nif­i­cance, nei­ther as a polem­i­cal for­mu­la­tion nor as a self-description by the the­o­rists com­monly sub­sumed under the name (such as Lukács, Korsch, Bloch, the Frank­furt School, Gram­sci, Lefeb­vre, etc.). Here, I fol­low Perry Anderson’s usage of the term in Con­sid­er­a­tions on West­ern Marx­ism(New York: Verso, 1987). As fruit­ful as the con­cept of West­ern Marx­ism might be as a heuris­tic model, its lim­its must be clearly shown; see the cri­tique of Ander­son by Wolf­gang Fritz Haug, “West­licher Marx­is­mus?” in Plu­raler Marx­is­mus, Bd. 2 (Ham­burg: Argu­ment, 1987) and Michael Krätke, “Marx­is­mus als Sozial­wis­senschaft” in Haug, Mate­ri­alien zum Historisch-kritischen Wörter­buch des Marx­is­mus (Ham­burg: Argu­ment, 1996), 77. 
  62. Wolf­gang Fritz Haug, Philoso­phieren mit Brecht und Gram­sci (Ham­burg: Argu­ment, 1996), 8. For a cri­tique of the “code word the­sis” with regard to Gramsci’s work, see Haug, “Ein­leitung,” in Anto­nio Gram­sci, Gefäng­nishefte 6. Philoso­phie der Praxis (Ham­burg: Argu­ment, 1995), 1195-1209. 
  63. Georg Lukács, “N. Bucharin: The­o­rie des his­torischen Mate­ri­al­is­mus (Rezen­sion)” in N. Bucharin/ A. Deborin: Kon­tro­ver­sen über dialek­tis­chen und mech­a­nis­tis­chen Mat­er­al­is­mus, 289, 284. 
  64. Anto­nio Gram­sci, “The Rev­o­lu­tion Against Cap­i­tal.” 
  65. A sci­en­tific psy­chol­ogy can­not be found in the thought of most rep­re­sen­ta­tives of Marx­ism, apart from pos­i­tive ref­er­ences to Pavlov’s behav­ior­ism. Psy­cho­analy­sis was mostly rejected, if not demo­nized as “bourgeois-decadent”. Hel­mut Dah­mer offers a crit­i­cal overview of such reac­tions in Libido und Gesellschaft. Stu­dien über Freud und die Freud­sche Linke (Frank­furt: Suhrkamp, 1982), 241-277; within the frame­work of West­ern Marx­ism, it was pri­mar­ily Lukács who dis­tin­guished him­self in the con­dem­na­tion of Freud. Gram­sci by his own admis­sion “was not able to study Freud’s the­o­ries” 
  66. As fur­ther char­ac­ter­is­tics of West­ern Marx­ism, Ander­son names the recourse to pre-Marxian phi­los­o­phy in order to clar­ify the method of a crit­i­cal social the­ory; the incor­po­ra­tion of con­tem­po­rary “bour­geois” the­o­ries: an eso­teric writ­ing style; a rather pes­simistic appraisal of his­tor­i­cal devel­op­ment markedly diver­gent from the tri­umphal­ist dic­tion of clas­si­cal Marx­ism and Marxism-Leninism; a pref­er­ence for prob­lems of aes­thet­ics. 
  67. For exam­ple, Erich Fromm’s Marx’s Con­cept of Man or Jür­gen Haber­mas’ “Recon­struc­tion of His­tor­i­cal Mate­ri­al­ism.” 
  68. The first attempts at a new read­ing of Marx already occurred in the 1920s, on the part of the Soviet authors Isaak Illich Rubin and Evgeny Pashuka­nis. See I.I. Rubin, Essays on Marx’s The­ory of Value, and Evgeny Pashuka­nis, The Gen­eral The­ory of Law and Marx­ism. Their aware­ness of prob­lems of aspects of Marx’s the­ory with regard to value and legal the­ory was not even matched in a rudi­men­tary way for a long time, in the East or the West. Only with the debates since the end of the 1960s did this change some­what. 
  69. As described by Hein­rich “Kom­men­tierte Lit­er­aturliste zur Kri­tik der poli­tis­chen Ökonomie,” in Elmar Alt­vater, Rolf Hecker, Michael Hein­rich, Petra Schaper-Rinkel, ed.,Kap­i­tal. doc. Das Kap­i­tal (Bd. 1) von Karl Marx in Schaubildern und Kom­mentaren (Mün­ster: West­fälis­ches Dampf­boot, 1999), 207; and Urs Jaeggi, “Einige Bemerkun­gen zur Ortho­doxie und zum Dog­ma­tismus im His­torischen Mate­ri­al­is­mus,” in Axel Hon­neth, ed.,The­o­rien des His­torischen Mate­ri­al­is­mus (Frank­furt: Suhrkamp, 1977), 146. It is also referred to under the label of “Neo-Marxism.” 
  70. As defined by Hans-Georg Back­haus, Dialek­tik der Wert­form. Unter­suchun­gen zur Marxschen Ökonomiekri­tik (Freiburg; ça ira, 1997). See also Hein­rich, “Kom­men­tierte Lit­er­aturliste,” 211. 
  71. See Hein­rich, Die Wis­senschaft vom Wert, and Hel­mut Brentel, Soziale Form und ökonomis­ches Objekt. Stu­dien zum Gegenstands- und Meth­o­d­en­ver­ständ­nis der Kri­tik der poli­tis­chen Ökonomie (Opladen: West­deutscher, 1989). 
  72. Con­cern­ing the so-called “state deriva­tion debate,” see Nor­bert Kost­ede, “Die neuere marx­is­tis­che Diskus­sion über den bürg­er­lichen Staat. Ein­führung – Kri­tik – Resul­tate,”Gesellschaft. Beiträge zur Marxschen The­o­rie (1976): 150-196; and Gerd Rudel, Die Entwick­lung der marx­is­tis­chen Staat­s­the­o­rie in der Bun­desre­pub­lik (Frank­furt: Campus-Verlag, 1981). 
  73. Ste­fan Breuer, Die Krise der Rev­o­lu­tion­s­the­o­rie. Neg­a­tive Verge­sellschaf­tung und Arbeitsmeta­physik bei Her­bert Mar­cuse (Frank­furt: Syn­dikat, 1977); Mohl, “Vere­len­dung und Rev­o­lu­tion”; Hel­mut König, Geist und Rev­o­lu­tion. Stu­dien zu Kant, Hegel und Marx(Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1981); or the writ­ings of the Kri­sis group. 
  74. Alfred Schmidt and Wal­ter Euch­ner, ed., Kri­tik der poli­tis­chen Ökonomie heute. 100 Jahre “Kap­i­tal” (Frank­furt: Europäis­che Ver­lagsanstalt, 1968). 
  75. The “crit­i­cal Marx­ism” of the Six­ties, of which Alfred Schmidt was the pri­mary advo­cate, empha­sizes the neg­a­tive and his­tor­i­cally lim­ited char­ac­ter and claim to valid­ity of a “mate­ri­al­ism of sec­ond nature,” but tends to regard method­olog­i­cal indi­vid­u­al­ism as an ade­quate descrip­tion of com­ing com­mu­nist rela­tions. The “sci­en­tific” Marx­ism of the Althusser school empha­sizes, against indi­vid­u­al­is­tic the­o­ries of a “con­sti­tut­ing sub­ject,” that actors are merely bear­ers of the rela­tions of pro­duc­tions, but on the basis of the ten­dency of its cat­e­gories to assume universal-historical char­ac­ter (Balibar’s com­bi­na­torics of lev­els, Althusser’s con­cepts of praxis and ide­ol­ogy), ele­vates the inde­pen­dence of rela­tions of pro­duc­tion to a sci­en­tific norm). 
  76. Back­haus, Dialek­tik der Wert­form, 11. 
  77. Ibid., 69. 
  78. Ibid. 
  79. See Louis Althusser, “From Cap­i­tal to Marx’s Phi­los­o­phy” in Louis Althusser and Eti­enne Bal­ibar, Read­ing Cap­i­tal
  80. See Althusser and Bal­ibar, Read­ing Cap­i­tal. The dif­fer­ence between the struc­tural­ist and the critical-reconstructive read­ing is not lim­ited to this point. Whereas the for­mer attempts to unmask Hegelian­ism as an inedaquate meta-discourse, for the lat­ter, ref­er­ence to Hegel on ques­tions of method­ol­ogy is often regarded as the royal road to under­stand­ing Marx’s work. 
  81. This is the sub­ti­tle of Heinrich’s book, Die Wis­senschaft vom Wert: see Back­haus’ cri­tique of his own the­o­ret­i­cal premises in the first two parts of his Mate­ri­alien (Back­haus, Dialek­tik der Wert­form, 132n). 
  82. For a crit­i­cal per­spec­tive on some aspects of these the­ses, see Dieter Wolf, Ware und Geld. Der dialek­tis­che Wider­spruch im Kap­i­tal (Ham­burg: VSA, 1958) (repub­lished in 2002 under the title Der dialek­tis­che Wider­spruch im Kap­i­tal). Wolf also crit­i­cizes ten­den­cies within the neue Marx-Lektüre that iden­tify Marx’s dialec­ti­cal method with log­i­cal con­tra­dic­tions, thus lend­ing Marx and his method a patina of irra­tional­ism; see his cri­tique of Col­letti and Göh­ler. Irra­tional­ist posi­tions are also found today by rep­re­sen­ta­tives of the Kri­sis and Exit groups and the Ini­tia­tive Sozial­is­tis­ches Forum Freiburg. 
  83. Marx, “Pref­ace to the First Ger­man Edi­tion.” 
  84. Schmidt, Con­cept of Nature, 41. 
  85. On Marx’s cri­tique of philoso­phies of his­tory, see: Hel­mut Fleis­cher, Marx­is­mus und Geschichte, (Frank­furt: Suhrkamp, 1975); Kittsteiner, “Bewusst­seins­bil­dung”; Andreas Arndt, Karl Marx. Ver­such über den Zusam­men­hang seiner The­o­rie (Bochum: Ger­mi­nal, 1985), 50-76; Rolf Hecker, Carl-Erich Voll­graf, Richard Sperl, ed., Geschichte und mate­ri­al­is­tis­che Geschicht­s­the­o­rie bei Marx (Ham­burg: Argu­ment, 1996). 
  86. G. Stiehler, quoted by Jaeggi, “Einige Bemerkun­gen,” 153. For a “cri­tique” of Marx that tries to sell this as the authen­tic posi­tion of Marx, see the usual works by Karl Pop­per. 
  87. Hel­mut Reichelt [1970], Zur logis­chen Struk­tur des Kap­i­tal­be­griffs bei Karl Marx (Freiburg: ça ira, 2001), 73. 
  88. See Hein­rich, Die Wis­senschaft vom Wert. 
  89. On this see Brentel 1989, chap­ter 5. 
  90. On this see Hein­rich, Die Wis­senschaft vom Wert, 380-384. 
  91. In the com­plete form in the so-called “Trin­ity For­mula” of the the­ory of the com­po­nents of value. For a cri­tique of neo­clas­si­cal eco­nom­ics, see Hein­rich, Die Wis­senschaft vom Wert,62-85. 
  92. Marx, “Cri­tique of Hegel’s Phi­los­o­phy of Right.” 
  93. Jan Hoff, Kri­tik der klas­sis­chen poli­tis­chen Ökonomie. Zur Rezep­tion der wert­the­o­retis­chen Ansätze ökonomis­cher Klas­siker durch Karl Marx (Köln: Pap­py­Rossa, 2004). 
  94. Marx, Cap­i­tal, Vol­ume 1
  95. Ibid. 
  96. Hoff, Kri­tik der klas­sis­chen poli­tis­chen Ökonomie, 78. 

Ingo Elbe is a researcher at the University of Oldenburg.

{ 2 comments… read them below or add one }

モンクレール フランス 価格 December 2, 2014 at 1:31 am

Theleads might be provided via various kinds of causes similarly to extensive, databases, through telephonic refers to or to advertisements. We support their software in order to his or her’s sales revenue emphasis with a wide-ranging lead generation programs app. using formative solution our organization treat your web marketing would like made by vigorouslycollaborating within your small business.


windows 8 activator December 8, 2014 at 3:19 pm

I like the helpful information you supply in your articles.
I will bookmark your weblog and check once more right here
frequently. I’m fairly certain I’ll be informed a lot of new stuff proper right here!
Good luck for the next!


Leave a Comment

{ 9 trackbacks }

Previous post:

Next post: